Sank's Glossary of Linguistics 
S-Sem

SANDHI

  1. (Phonology) The ways in which speech sounds influence each other when they are neighbors is of great interest to contemporary phoneticians and phonologists (cf. assimilation and coalescence), but the subject is also one which interested the Sanskrit grammarians of India (who introduced the term) over two thousand years ago. The notion of sandhi is used mainly in the area between morphology and phonology, and it is not much used in the study of pronunciation. It is most commonly found in discussion of tone languages and the contextual influences on tones. | Peter Roach, 2011
  2. (Phonology) Literally, juncture phenomena: assimilation or other combinatory phenomena that cross word boundaries. Example: Deletion of /t/ in the Dutch phrase post brengen. | Utrecht Lexicon of Linguistics, 2001
  3. (Morphophonology) From Sanskrit सधि, lit. 'joining'. Any of a wide variety of sound changes that occur at morpheme or word boundaries. Examples include fusion of sounds across word boundaries and the alteration of one sound depending on nearby sounds or the grammatical function of the adjacent words. Sandhi belongs to morphophonology.
     Sandhi occurs in many languages, e.g. in the phonology of South Asian languages (especially Sanskrit, Tamil, Sinhala, Telugu, Marathi, Hindi, Pali, Kannada, Bengali, Assamese, Malayalam). Many dialects of British English show linking and intrusive R. | Wikipedia, 2024
See Also TONE SANDHI.

SATELLITE-FRAMING
See VERB-FRAMING.

SATISFACTION
(Syntax) A probe H interacts with feature F by copying F back to H. A probe H is satisfied by feature G iff copying G back to H terminates further probing for G by H. | Amy Rose Deal, 2015

SATISFACTION THEORY OF PRESUPPOSITION
(Pragmatics) The idea underlying the satisfaction theory of presupposition is a simple and attractive one. It is that the utterance of a sentence changes the context in which it is made, and that the way in which a sentence affects its context determines its projection characteristics. Presuppositions that are triggered within the scope of a negation operator, for example, tend to "escape from" that scope because of the way negated sentences interact with their contexts. This picture is appealing because it implies that the projection problem doesn't call for a solution at all: the problem simply dissolves once we have a theory of context change, which we want to have anyhow. | Bart Geurts, 1996

SCALAR ADVERB

  1. (Semantics) Such as perhaps, certainly, never, often, very, completely. | Isabelle Lorge and Janet B. Pierrehumbert, 2023
  2. (Semantics) The adverbs of degree, manner, and frequency whose positive and negative counterparts display the opposing word order behavior illustrated in (1)-(6) all have scalar meanings.

    Hungarian

    1. János
      John
      nagyon
      very.much
      el
      PRT
      -fáradt.
      got.tired
      'John got tired very much.'
    2. János
      John
      alig
      barely
      fáradt
      got.tired
      el.
      PRT
      'John barely got tired.'
    3. János
      John
      jól
      well
      meg-oldotta
      PRT solved
      a
      the
      feladatot.
      problem
      'John solved the problem well.'
    4. János
      John
      rosszul
      badly
      oldotta
      solved
      meg
      PRT
      a
      the
      feladatot.
      problem
      'John solved the problem badly.'
    5. János
      John
      gyakran
      often
      el
      PRT
      -késik.
      late.is
      'John is often late.'
    6. János
      John
      ritkán
      seldom
      késik
      late.is
      el.
      PRT
      'John is seldom late.'

     Ernst (2002) calls them gradable adverbs. Kiefer (1964) attributes to them a [+contrast] feature, encoding the intuition that they come in pairs representing opposite values in the positive and negative domains of a bidirectional scale. It is adverbs in the negative domain of bidirectional scales that are obligatorily focused.
     Being scalar elements, these adverbs are subject to the generalizations formulated in (7), (8) and (9).

    1.  The meaning of a scalar element n in natural language is 'at least n'.
    2.  The 'at least n'; 'n or more' reading of a scalar modifier in the negative domain of a bidirectional scale leads to a semantic anomaly.
    3.  A scalar expression denoting a negative value in a bidirectional scale must be focused.

     Thus a scalar adverb of degree, manner, or frequency denoting a scalar value n means 'at least n'—owing to the fact that section n of the given scale also represents a subsection of the higher values of the same scale. In case a pair of adverbs establishes a bidirectional scale (e.g. nagyon 'very much' / alig 'barely', szépen 'beautifully' / csúnyán 'uglily', gyakran 'frequently' / ritkán 'rarely), the adverb denoting a scalar value in the negative domain of the scale resists this kind of upward extending interpretation. On a bidirectional scale, a positive scalar value does not entail a negative one, e.g., very much does not entail barely, beautifully does not entail uglily, and frequently does not entail rarely—hence barely cannot be understood as an understatement for very much, uglily cannot be understood as an understatement for beautifully, and rarely cannot be understood as an understatement for frequently. The upward extending interpretation of these adverbs must be blocked, and it is blocked by their obligatory focusing. | Katalin É Kiss, 2007

SCALAR EXPRESSION
(Semantics; Pragmatics) An expression which involves scales in its interpretation. Scalar expressions include logical quantifiers (e.g. all, some), quantifying determiners (e.g. few, half), quantifying time expressions (e.g. always, often), scalar adverbs (almost, only, more than), and scalar predicates (e.g. love, like; must, shall). The nature of such scales is controversial, being conceived both in terms of strength (e.g. "all is stronger than some") and of direction (almost and more activate a scale which is in a positive direction, by contrast with the negative direction of only and less than). | David Crystal, 2000

SCALAR IMPLICATURE

  1. (Pragmatics) Where a weaker term on a scale implicates the negation of a stronger term.

    1. John ate some of the chocolates.
      The implicature: John did not eat all of the chocolates.

    Some includes the meaning of all, but, given the Maxim of Quantity, the speaker will only use some if he is not in a position to use all. Hence, his use of some implicates that there were chocolates not eaten by John. Notice that an implicature can be cancelled, when the speaker explicitly strengthens his utterance:

    1. John ate some of the chocolates, in fact, he ate all of the chocolates.

    Scalar implicatures are an instance of generalized implicatures (that normally follow from the utterance), in distinction to particularized implicatures (that one follows in special contexts). (Grice 1975, Levinson 1983) | Utrecht Lexicon of Linguistics, 2001
  2. (Pragmatics) The inference that a speaker chose a less informative statement because the more informative statement is not true (e.g., some implies some and not all)
    1. Some sea otters sleep on their backs.
       → Not all sea otters sleep on their backs.
     | Anna Papafragou, 2023
  3. (Pragmatics) (1) is a quantity (or scalar) implicature: the speaker implicates the denial of a proposition stronger than the one said.
    1. Not all athletes smoke.
     | Wayne Davis, 2005

SCALAR PREDICATE

  1. (Semantics) We take a scalar predicate to be a predicate that expresses a scale, where a scale is defined as in (1).

    1. A scale is "a dense linearly ordered set of points, or 'degrees', where the ordering is relativized to a dimension." (Kennedy 1999)

     Thus, a scale must include three elements: a set of degrees [D], with a linear ordering [R], in a specific dimension [Δ]. Scales associated with scalar predicates (e.g. adjectives) vary in structure. An adjective like Spanish alto 'tall' denotes a set of degrees of height which are linearly ordered. This scale has neither a minimal nor a maximal value and is therefore an open scale. On the other hand, an adjective like despierto 'awake' also denotes a set of linearly ordered degrees of awakeness, but in this case, the scale has a minimal value, i.e. there is a minimal positive point of awakeness below which one can no longer predicate the awakeness of something. It is therefore a lower-closed scale. | Isabel Oltra-Massuet and Isabel Pérez-Jiménez, 2014
  2. (Semantics) If we wish to preserve the notion that the use of a scalar predicate always involves some comparison, we can say that the use of a verb denoting a scalar change involves the comparison of the degree to which a scalar property holds of an object at the beginning of the event and the degree to which the same property holds of the object at the end of the event (Kennedy and Levin 2008). Since the standard of comparison is inherent in the meaning of the verb—the value of the attribute at the beginning of the event—it doesn't have to be contextually specified. Therefore, a sentence such as (1) can be appropriate even if a person's hair got a bit longer but is still considered short.

    1. His hair lengthened.

     | Malka Rappaport Hovav, 2014

SCALAR QUANTIFIER

  1. (Semantics; Pragmatics) Scalar quantifiers are often used as a case study to illustrate the interaction between semantics (the truth-conditional content of utterances) and pragmatics (the inferential analysis component of language). Both semantics and pragmatics contribute to the interpretation of standard scalar expressions such as some, thereby allowing them to have two interpretations: the weak reading ('some and possibly all') and the strong reading ('some but not all'). Another class of scalar quantifiers, numerals, is often compared with standard scalars because they, too, can have two interpretations: the exact reading, (two means 'two and no more') or the at-least reading (two means 'two and possibly more'). | Qingqing Wu, 2013
  2. (Semantics; Pragmatics) Classically, the meaning of quantifiers is described in terms of clearcut binary truth conditions (e.g. Barwise and Cooper 1981, Peters and Westerståhl 2008). For example, the sentence schema Some of the As are Bs is true just in case there is at least one A that is also a B. On top of that, it is widely held that the scalar quantifier some, if used in the appropriate contexts, conveys a scalar implicature, roughly, that some but not all of the As are Bs (cf. Grice 1975, Levinson 1983). | Michael Franke, 2014

SCALE OF UNIQUENESS
(Semantics; Pragmatics) The multi-layered approach to DPs we've pursued finds a correlate in the Uniqueness Scale of Löbner (1985, 2011), further developed in Ortmann (2014), who proposes "a continuum of types of uniqueness" (Sichel to appear [2019]). Semantic uniqueness involves reference due to a noun's inherent meaning ('the sun'). Pragmatic uniqueness comes from the context, such as deictic or anaphoric ('the man'):

  1. Scale of uniqueness
    deictic SN (sortal noun) < anaphoric SN < SN with establishing relative clause < definite associate anaphors < IN/FN1 < proper names < 3rd person personal pronouns < 2nd and 1st person personal pronouns

 Ortmann discusses languages like Fering (Northern Frisian) that display a split in their definite article systems, one lexical form corresponding to the upper functions of the scale and another to the lower ones.
 The Uniqueness Scale relates straightforwardly to our multi-layered DP analysis of Balearic Catalan and French Picard: the s- article in Balearic Catalan and the ch- article in Picard map to the higher part of the scale; the l- article of Balearic Catalan and Picard map to the lower part of the scale. Thus, there is a clear correspondence between the uniqueness scale and the multi-layered DP analysis: the deictic and anaphoric SNs correspond to DP1, and the IN/FNs correspond to DP2.
 Ortmann's implementation of the Uniqueness Scale makes two important predictions:

  1. a. Definite articles become more obligatory as we move higher up the scale, less obligatory as we move down the scale.
    b. Over time, the use of definite articles will spread downward along the scale, not upward.
 | Judy B. Bernstein, Francisco Ordóñez, and Francesc Roca, 2020

SCOPE AMBIGUITY

  1. (Semantics) The kind of ambiguity that arises when an operator can enter into different scope relations with other scoped elements.
     (1) has the two readings, (2) and (3). In (2) every farmer is construed as having scope over a donkey and in (3) a donkey is construed as having scope over every farmer:

    1. Every farmer loves a donkey.
    2. For every farmer there is a donkey such that he loves him.
    3. There is a donkey such that every farmer loves him.

     (May 1977, Montague 1974) | Utrecht Lexicon of Linguistics, 2001
  2. (Semantics) An ambiguity that occurs when two quantifiers or similar expressions can take scope over each other in different ways in the meaning of a sentence.

    1. Every man loves a woman.
    2. Every student did not pass the exam.

     Let's look at (1) to see the ambiguity. The more prominent meaning of (1) is that for every man, there is a woman, and it's possible that each man loves a different woman. But the sentence also has a second possible meaning, which says that there is one particular woman who is loved by every man. This reading becomes clearer if we continue the example by adding namely Brigitte Bardot.
     To further underline the difference, have a look at the two readings represented in first-order logic.
    1. x.MAN (x) → (∃y.WOMAN (y) ∧ LOVE ( x, y))
    2. y.WOMAN (y) ∧ (∀x.MAN (x) → LOVE (x, y))
     We see that (1) has two different meanings: it is ambiguous. Moreover, there is no good reason to assume that the ambiguity should be syntactic. So we can say that scope ambiguities are genuine semantic ambiguities. It is important to observe here that both readings are made up of the same material (the semantic representations of the quantified NPs every man and a woman, and the nuclear scope love). The only difference is the way in which the material is put together.
     Example (2) shows that not only quantifiers can give rise to scope ambiguities. If you find (2) a little odd, you can play the same game with the German Jeder Student hat nicht bestanden. In (2) it is the relative scope of the quantifier and the negation that is ambiguous. The two readings mean that either every single student failed, or, respectively, that not everyone of the students passed.
     In formulae:
    1. x.STUDENT (x) → ¬PASS (x)
    2. ¬∀x.(STUDENT (x) → PASS (x))
     | Aljoscha Burchardt, Stephan Walter, Alexander Koller, Michael Kohlhase, Patrick Blackburn and Johan Bos, 2003

SCRAMBLING
(Syntax) A phenomenon wherein sentences can be formulated using a variety of different word orders without any change in meaning. Scrambling often results in a discontinuity, since the scrambled expression can end up at a distance from its head. Scrambling does not occur in English, but it is frequent in languages with freer word order, such as German, Russian, Persian and Turkic languages. The term was coined by Haj Ross in his 1967 dissertation and is widely used in present work, particularly with the generative tradition.
 Typical instances:

  1. German
    daß
    that
    der
    the
    Mann
    man
    der
    the
    Frau
    woman
    die
    the
    Bohnen
    beans
    gab
    gave
    'that the man gave the woman the beans'
  2. daß der Mann die Bohnen der Frau gab
  3. daß der Frau der Mann die Bohnen gab
  4. daß der Frau die Bohnen der Mann gab
  5. daß die Bohnen der Mann der Frau gab
  6. daß die Bohnen der Frau der Mann gab
 These examples illustrate typical cases of scrambling in the midfield of a subordinate clause in German. All six clauses are acceptable, whereby the actual order that appears is determined by pragmatic considerations such as emphasis. If one takes the first clause (clause 1) as the basic order, then scrambling has occurred in clauses 2-6. The three constituents der Mann, der Frau, and die Bohnen have been scrambled. | Wikipedia, 2023

SECONDARY PREDICATE
(Syntax) A (mostly adjectival) predicative expression that conveys information about the subject or the object but is not the main predicate of the clause. This structure may be analyzed in many different ways. These may be resultative, as in (1) and (2), or descriptive (also called depictive), as in (3).

  1. She painted the town red.
  2. The film left me cold.
  3. Susan walked around naked. (Depictive over the subject, or subject-oriented depictive.)
  4. John ate the meat raw. (Depictive over the object, or object-oriented depictive.)
  5. All men are created equal.
 Optional depictive secondary predicates are viewed as predicative adjuncts by some linguists. (Huddleston and Pullum 2002) | Wikipedia, 2021

SELECTIVE OPACITY EFFECTS
(Syntax) Configurations in which the same constituent is opaque for some operations but transparent for others. Classical observations of selective opacity lie in the realm of movement. Finite clauses, for instance, are opaque for A-movement but transparent for Ā-extraction, a pattern that generalizes beyond the A/Ā distinction. | Stefan Keine, 2019
See Also SEMANTIC TRANSPARENCY.

SELOSÍSMO
(Syntax) Mexican speech has a non-standard use of se los/las to express a plural indirect object and a singular direct object; something that would normatively be expressed as se lo/la, the classic example being se los dije [a ellos] rather than se lo dije. The author proposes the name selosísmo to define the phenomenon that, until now, has had multiple names. | Riley VanMeter, 2023

SEMANTIC BLEACHING
(Semantics; Diachronic) Or, semantic loss, semantic reduction, desemanticization, and weakening. The loss or reduction of meaning in a word as a result of semantic change.

 | Richard Nordquist, 2018

SEMANTIC CONTENT

  1. (Semantics) A complex expression relative to a context c has a referential content that is the result of combining the referential contents of its constituent terms relative to the context c in accord with the semantic composition rules corresponding to the syntactic structure of that expression. The result of this latter process is a genuine level of semantic value, which we shall call the semantic content of that complex expression relative to the context c. The semantic content of a lexical item relative to a context c is, on this view, its referential content in that context. | Jeffrey C. King and Jason Stanley, 2005
  2. (Examples) 

SEMANTIC DUPLICATION

  1. (Computational; Semantics) In online document collections, users often wish to identify whether incoming documents have close semantic matches in the existing collection, i.e. the specific content or topic of the incoming document matches with that of a previously published document. We consider semantic duplication to occur over a document pair {A, B} in one of two forms:
    1. Subsumption: where A properly subsumes B (i.e. B ⊂ A).
    2. Synonymy: where A and B have identical semantic content (i.e. A ≡ B), that is the two documents subsume each other.
     | Andrew MacKinlay and Timothy Baldwin, 2009
  2. (Computational; Semantics) Language models need to be taught all basic facts, but teaching them these basic facts while also testing them on these facts necessarily constitutes semantic duplication.
     Consider the following example:
    1. a. Train set question: "What formula could one use to calculate the area of a circle?"
      b. Test set question: "What is the formula for the area of a circle?"
     These questions are semantically equivalent. There's no way to teach a model basic factual questions without having semantic duplicates like this.  | Jade, 2023

SEMANTIC EMPTINESS
(Examples)

SEMANTIC EXTENDEDNESS
(Semantics) The basis conceptual category for entities. Just as entities may or may not have extension in space (extended or nonextended), so may events have (or have not) temporal extension by virtue of the nature of their internal contour. Durative events are extended; punctual events are nonextended.
 Both progressive and habitual aspect involve extendedness: The former extends from within the event; the latter from without. | William Frawley, 1992

SEMANTIC EXTENSION
(Semantics) Involves applying a word to something that falls outside of the word's linguistically specified denotation, on the basis of a principled relationship between the literal and the extended denotation, e.g. rabbit meaning 'animal' is extended to mean the meat of that animal, mouth meaning the oral cavity is extended to mean the opening of a cave, based on its resemblance to a mouth.
 In the historical linguistics literature, semantic extension is widely acknowledged as playing a key role in semantic change and grammaticalization, a word's journey from a lexical, concept-encoding word to a functional item with a more abstract grammatical meaning (see e.g. Givón 1979, Bybee, Perkins, and Pagliuca 1994, Heine, Claudi, and Hünnemeyer 1991, Heine 1997, Haspelmath 1998, Traugott and Dasher 2001). | Josephine Bowerman and Kenny Smith, 2022

SEMANTIC FORMULA
(Pragmatics) Represents "the means by which a particular speech act is accomplished, in terms of the primary content of an utterance" (Bardovi-Harlig and Hartford 1991). A semantic formula refers to "a word, phrase, or sentence that meets a particular semantic criterion or strategy; any one or more of these can be used to perform the act in question" (Cohen 1996). For instance:

  1. I am so sorry that I cannot make it, because I have an appointment with my wife. Thanks for your invitation.
 This example includes four semantic formulas:
  1. Statement of regret (I am so sorry).
  2. Negative willingness ability (I cannot make it).
  3. Reason (because I have an appointment with my wife).
  4. Appreciation (Thanks for your invitation).
 | Zhao Chunli, 2016

SEMANTIC IDENTITY CONDITION
(Syntax) The SIC accepts the view that there is a semantic relation between E (elided clause) and A (antecedent clause) to license sluicing (see Dalrymple et al. 1991, Hardt 1999, Ginzburg and Sag 2001, Merchant 2001, van Craenenbroeck 2010, van Craenenbroeck and Merchant 2013, a.o.). The semantic view, elaborated by Merchant (2001) and others, requires a mutual entailment relationship between the elided material and its antecedent. The semantic entailment condition allows examples like (1) since the antecedent clause in (2) and the elided clause in (3) entail each other and thus the latter can be deleted:

  1. He resembled someone, but I do not know who.
  2. Antecedent clause ⟦A⟧ = ∃x (He resembled x)
  3. Elided clause ⟦E⟧ = ∃x (He resembled x)
 | Jong-Bok Kim, 2015

SEMANTIC LOAN
(Sociolinguistics) A process of borrowing semantic meaning (rather than lexical items) from another language. The complete word in the borrowing language already exists; the change is that its meaning is extended to include another meaning that its existing translation has in the lending language.
 A typical example is the French word souris, which means 'mouse' (the animal). After the English word mouse acquired the additional sense of 'computer mouse,' when French speakers began speaking of computer mice, they did so by extending the meaning of their own word souris by analogy with how English speakers had extended the meaning of mouse. (Had French speakers started using the word mouse, that would have been a borrowing; had they created a new lexeme out of multiple French morphemes, as with disque dur for 'hard disk,' that would have been a calque.) | Wikipedia, 2022

SEMANTIC POTENCY

  1. (Semantics) The capacity of a word in producing primary, secondary and tertiary levels of meaning. | Joby John, 2018
  2. (Semantics) We call the semantic potency of a code (language) the number of meanings it distinguishes within its noetic field (De Mauro 2008). | Karmen Lazri and Irena Ndreu, 2023

SEMANTIC SHIFT

  1. (Semantics) The use of slang in our society today has grown tremendously, and as slang becomes more popular, words and their meanings often change to adapt to users' needs. Dialect is such a fundamental part of society as it allows people to verbally communicate with each other in unique ways. As the use of the internet has increased over the past few decades, humans have created different uses for the same word, with slang terms in particular. This change in meaning of a word is what linguists have classified as a semantic shift. | Ali Dimaio, 2023
  2. (Semantics) Words and morphemes may seem to any individual speaker of a language to be timeless and unchanging in their meanings. And while this may be true for most of the words any given language user knows, changes in meaning over time are actually quite common. Many of our words are no longer what they once were. This process is generally known as semantic shift, or semantic change.
     The changes that words and morphemes go through can be classified into a number of different kinds of processes. A word can gain a more extensive meaning over time (broadening), or come to apply to a smaller set of circumstances (narrowing). Or how good or bad a word is taken to be can drift, too: a morpheme can generally improve in meaning (amelioration), or become more negative instead (pejoration). Sometimes, the meaning of a word can become weaker over time, so that a word with an extreme meaning becomes softer (weakening). Finally, if the evolution of the word's meaning doesn't really seem to fit a given category, but it's clearly changed, we just can refer to this as shift.
     We can find these kinds of changes in pretty much every language in the world we've documented, and there's no limit on the number of time a given word can have its meaning change. Every generation of language learners can decide anew what they want a word to mean, and shift the word's use over time. And when they make their adjustments, they do it along the same lines people have made changes before. | The Ling Space, 2016

SEMANTIC TRANSPARENCY
(Semantics) This term aims to capture the intuitive difference felt between compounds like hogwash, meaning 'nonsense', and a compound like milkman. In the literature, semantic transparency is defined in two main ways. One is the idea that it can be linked to meaning predictability. Plag (2003) states that words are semantically transparent if "their meaning is predictable on the basis of the word-formation rule according to which they have been formed."
 The second kind of definition uses analyzability rather than predictability. A classic example is Zwitserlood (1994), who writes that "[t]he meaning of a fully transparent compound is synchronically related to the meaning of its composite words". In this sense, milkman clearly is transparent because any possible usage will allow linking the interpretation in some way to the meanings of the constituent parts. | Melanie J. Bell and Martin Schäfer, 2013

SEMANTIC UNITY

  1. (Semantics) In contrast to studies that have focused on the syntactic properties of English -self pronouns (myself, yourself, etc.), this paper investigates the semantic and pragmatic contributions these forms make in different structural contexts, including not only appositive uses, but also reflexives and a wide variety of so-called exceptional uses, such as logophoric expressions and picture noun phrases. An extensive examination of data from a collection of spoken and written texts reveals that -self pronouns in different structural environments nevertheless exhibit the same semantic and pragmatic characteristics. The structurally diverse assemblage of reflexives, emphatics, and a list of other exceptions are shown to have semantic unity, since the same message effects are seen in all of these environments, including argument and appositive, reflexive and emphatic, as well as what are traditionally described as discourse-based uses. | Nancy Stern, 2004
  2. (Stylistics) Textual unity and semantic unity are two important features of a text. Different linguistic items present in a text weave together to give textual unity to the text and at deep level these linguistic features contribute to produce unified meanings which create semantic unity in the text. Enkvist (1987) also believes that semantic connections take two forms i.e. a connection at surface level called cohesion and a connection at more profound level takes the form of coherence. A text as a cohesive semantic unit must have surface cohesion and overall coherence in order to present a flow of thought and meanings in the text. | Amina Shahzadi, Rahat Chaudhary, and Abdul Ghaffar Bhatti, 2022

 

Page Last Modified September 21, 2024

 
B a c k   T o   I n d e x