Sank's Glossary of Linguistics
Ag-Al |
AGENT-BASED MODELING
- (Sociolinguistics) A technique where you have a screen full of hundreds of little creatures we call "agents". The idea is that they interact with each other on the screen, and each agent is independent in the sense that it has its own dialect features and language abilities, but then as it comes into contact with another agent, it can change. Its dialect may change.
It's a powerful tool that's been used in medicine and social science, and so we're applying it to dialect and language research as a way to model how languages change and even possibly predict the future of what direction a language might take. | ?
- (Epidemiology) Computer simulations that are used to study the interactions between people, things, places, and time. They are stochastic models built from the bottom up meaning individual agents are assigned certain attributes. The agents are programmed to behave and interact with other agents and the environment in certain ways. These interactions produce emergent effects that may differ from effects of individual agents. Agent-based modeling differs from traditional, regression-based methods in that, like systems dynamics modeling, it allows for the exploration of complex systems that display non-independence of individuals and feedback loops in causal mechanisms. It is not limited to observed data and can be used to model the counterfactual or experiments that may be impossible or unethical to conduct in the real world.
However, agent-based modeling is not without its limitations. The data parameters (such as the reproductive rate for infectious diseases) are often difficult to find in the literature. In addition, the validity of the model can be difficult to assess, particularly when modeling unobserved associations. Overall, agent-based models provide an additional tool for assessing the impacts of exposures on outcomes. It is particularly useful when interrelatedness, reciprocity, and feedback loops are known or suspected to exist or when real world experiments are not possible. | Mailman School of Public Health, ?
AGENT FOCUS
- (Syntax) Morphologically ergative languages display asymmetries in the extraction of core arguments: while absolutive arguments (transitive objects and intransitive subjects) extract freely, ergative arguments (transitive subjects) cannot. This falls under the label syntactic ergativity (see, e.g. Dixon 1972, 1994 Manning 1996, Polinsky 2017). These extraction asymmetries are found in many languages of the Mayan family, where in order to extract transitive subjects (for focus, questions, or relativization), a special construction known as the Agent Focus (AF) must be used. These AF constructions have been described as syntactically and semantically transitive because they contain two non-oblique DP arguments, but morphologically intransitive because the verb appears with only a single agreement marker and takes an intransitive status suffix (Aissen 1999, Stiebels 2006). Some morphologically ergative languages exhibit extraction asymmetries, while others do not. | J. Coon, P. M. Pedro, and Omer Preminger, 2014
- (Grammar) One of the most discussed issues in Mayan linguistics is a verb form that is restricted to a particular set of constructions, namely relative clauses, content questions and focus constructions. Many Mayan languages feature this so-called Agent Focus (AF) verb form, which is used, roughly speaking, when the agent of a transitive verb is realized in the immediately preverbal position (e.g., Jakaltek [Craig 1979], Tzotzil [Aissen 1999], Ixil [Ayres 1983], Tz'utujil [Dayley 1985], Mam [England 1983], K'iche' [Mondloch 1981, Larsen 1987]). The following focus constructions from K'iche' illustrate the regular transitive and the AF verb form of the predicate ch'ay 'hit'. The focus construction in (1) is formed on the regular transitive predicate where both arguments are cross-referenced: the agent by the prefix aa- '2SG.A' and the patient by the (zero) prefix Ø- '3SG.B'. The focus construction in (2) is formed with the AF verb form which only cross-references one argument (here, the agent) by at- '2SG.B' and it is marked by the
suffix -ow. (The examples are from Larsen 1987. The glosses are his.)
aree
FOCUS
ri
the
achii
man
x-Ø-aa-ch'ay-o.
PERFV-3SG.B-2SG.A-hit-PF
'It was the man that you hit.'
aree
FOCUS
ri
the
at
you
x-at-ch'ay-ow
PERFV-2SG.B-hit-FOC.AP
ri
the
achii.
man
'You were the one who hit the man.'
Although the Mayan AF verb form occurs in roughly the same constructions across the Mayan languages that have it, there exists quite some inter-language variation with respect to the particular conditions under which the AF verb form is realized. | Judith Tonhauser, 2003
AGGLUTINATIVE LANGUAGE
- (Morphology; Typology) A type of synthetic language with morphology that primarily uses agglutination. Words may contain different morphemes to determine their meanings, but all of these morphemes (including stems and affixes) tend to remain unchanged after their unions, although this is not a rule: for example, Finnish is a typical agglutinative language, but morphemes are subject to (sometimes unpredictable) consonant alternations called consonant gradation. Despite the occasional outliers, agglutinative languages tend to have more easily deducible word meanings if compared to fusional languages, which allow unpredictable modifications in either or both the phonetics or spelling of one or more morphemes within a word. This usually results in a shortening of the word, or it provides easier pronunciation. | Wikipedia, 2022
- (Morphology; Typology) Turkish, like Hungarian and Finnish, is an agglutinating language, building up sometimes extremely complex word forms through an extensive range of suffixes. | Phillip Durrant, 2013
- (Morphology; Typology) The agglutinating type is indicated by:
- Words are formed by a root and a clearly detachable sequence of affixes, each of them expressing a separate item of meaning. Affixes are widely employed to indicate the relationships between words. Therefore, there are few or no independent relational elements (e.g., pronouns, pre-/postposition, articles, etc.), and a wide use of nominal cases.
- Very high matching between morphs and morphemes. Morphs are loosely joined together; consequently it is very easy to determine the boundaries between them.
- Each affix carries only one meaning: no cases of homonymy or synonymy among affixes; the semantic structure is directly reflected in the morphological articulation of the word; no principled limits to the number of affixes in a word.
- Word-class distinction is minimal: the same affixes tend to occur with roots belonging to different parts of speech (e.g., personal endings to nouns, case endings to verbs); almost the same morphology for adjectives and verbs. No inflectional classes, no gender distinction.
- Derivational affixes are widely employed in word formation. The distinction between inflectional and deriva￾tional affixes is slight. Many affixes reveal their lexical origin to some extent. The latter feature, together with the tendency of affixes to form autonomous syllables and to be relatively unconstrained in number, results in words that are quite long.
- Relatively fixed word order. Agreement is almost completely absent.
| Gilang Febrian, Ulfa Novitasari, and Arif Hidayat, 2022
AGR
- (Syntax) The person and number feature complex in finite INFL.
Since Pollock (1989): a functional head containing agreement features and/or an agreement suffix which projects its own syntactic X-bar schema called Agreement Phrase (AgrP). (Belletti 1991, Chomsky 1981, Ouhalla 1990, and Pollock 1989) | Utrecht Lexicon of Linguistics, 2001
- (Syntax) The main proposal of Pollock (1989) is that the Infl node be split open, as it were, and that each of the elements contained in this node (Tense, Agr, and Negation) head its own maximal projection. Under this proposal, the structure of the smallest sentence
containing negation is as follows:
TP
/\
/ \
/ \
T'
/\
/ \
/ \
T0 NegP
/\
/ \
/ \
AgrP
/\
/ \
/ \
Agr'
/\
/ \
/ \
Agr0 VP
One of Pollock's major goals is to provide evidence for the existence of AgrP, a maximal projection below Tense (or Negation, when this is present) and above the VP. | Sabine Iatridou, 1990
AGREE
- (Syntax) A relation between two matching active categories eliminating the uninterpretable features activating these categories. (Chomsky 1999) | Utrecht Lexicon of Linguistics, 2001
- (Syntax) In the Minimalist Program, agree allows the checking of features without movement—for example, checking the Case feature on an object DP without moving the object. The checking feature (probe) must c-command the checked feature (goal). | David Crystal, 2008
- (Syntax) A syntactic operation that is standardly taken to assign a value to an unvalued feature on one element (called the Probe), by copying a compatible value from another element (called the Goal). It is usually defined as follows (compare Chomsky 2000, 2001, 2008):
Agree (standard definition)
α can Agree with β iff:
- α carries at least one unvalued and uninterpretable feature and β carries a matching interpretable and valued feature.
- α c-commands β.
- β is the closest Goal to α.
- β bears an unvalued uninterpretable feature of its own.
The fourth of these conditions, often called the Activity Condition, has been shown not to hold universally (see Baker 2008, Halpert 2019, Oxford 2017, a.o.). | Neil Myler, 2023
- (Syntax) The agreement relation between the arguments and their co-indexing by the verbal morphology has been captured in the generative Minimalist framework by the syntactic operation Agree (Chomsky 2000, 2001). Under Agree, a head and a phrase (or technically, the head of that phrase) share features, typically φ-features: person, number, and gender. The phrase has values for these features, for example the subject in (1) nikhúle 'mouse' is specified as [person: 3], [number: SG], [gender: C]:
Makhuwa (Southern Bantu):
Ni-khúlé
5-mouse
ni-ni-ḿ-vár-á
5SM-PRS.CJ-1OM-grab-FV
naphulú.
1a.frog
'A/the mouse grabs a/the frog.'
Ma-khúlé
6-mice
a-ni-ḿ-vár-á
6SM-PRS.CJ-1OM-grab-FV
naphulú.
1a.frog
'(The) mice grab a/the frog.'
Ni-khúlé
5-mouse
ni-n-aá-vár-á
5SM-PRC.CJ-2OM-grab-FV
anaphúlu.
2a.frog
'A/the mouse grabs (the) frogs.'
The head, on the other hand, does not inherently have these features, but "needs" them. This is modelled as uninterpretable unvalued features on the head, which probe the structure for valuation; for uφ-features we indicate this as [person: _], [number: _], [gender: _]. The unvalued features are therefore also called the probe. As soon as the probe encounters a
matching goal, namely a DP that can value features of the probe, the two agree, which means that unvalued features on the probe are valued. | Jenneke van der Wal, 2022
AGREEMENT
- (Grammar) A traditional term used in grammatical theory and description to refer to a formal relationship between elements, whereby a form of one word requires a corresponding form of another (i.e. the forms agree). In Latin, for example, agreement between elements is of central importance, being one of the main means of expressing grammatical relationships in the absence of fixed patterns of word-order. The term concord has been more widely used in linguistic studies, but in generative linguistics "agreement" resurfaced with a new range of application. | David Crystal, 2008
- (Syntax) A widespread syntactic situation in which a target element agrees with a controller element in some morphosyntactic feature.
"The term 'agreement' commonly refers to some systematic covariance between a semantic or formal property of one element and a formal property of another." (Steele 1978)
- Agreement of article and adjective with noun in number and gender (Spanish examples)
a. la casa nueva ('the new house')
b. el libro nuevo ('the new book')
c. las casas nuevas ('the new houses')
d. los libros nuevos ('the new books')
- Agreement of verb with subject noun phrase (German examples)
a. ich kaufe ('I buy')
b. du kaufst ('you(SG) buy')
c. er kauft ('he buys')
d. wir kaufen ('we buy')
e. ihr kauft ('you(PL) buy')
f. sie kaufen ('they buy')
(Corbett 2006, Steele 1978) | Utrecht Lexicon of Linguistics, 2001
ALIENABLE/INALIENABLE POSSESSION
(Grammar) A type of possession in which a noun is obligatorily possessed by its possessor. Nouns or nominal affixes in an inalienable possession relationship cannot exist independently or be "alienated" from their possessor. For example, a hand implies '(someone's) hand', even if it is severed from the whole body. Likewise, a father implies '(someone's) father'. Inalienable nouns include body parts, kinship terms, and part-whole relations. Many languages reflect this distinction, but they vary in the way they mark inalienable possession. Cross-linguistically, inalienability correlates with many morphological, syntactic, and semantic properties.
In general, the alienable–inalienable distinction is an example of a binary possessive class system.
Alienable possession is generally used for tangible items which one might cease to own at some point (e.g. my money) whereas inalienable possession refers to a perpetual relationship which cannot be readily severed (e.g. my mother). | Wikipedia, 2017
See Also INALIENABLE POSSESSION.
ALIGN
(Optimality Theory) A constraint:
ALIGN
The final edge of a Morphological Word (MWord) corresponds to the final edge of a syllable.
ALIGN belongs to the family of constraints which govern the relation between prosody and grammatical structure. Considerable further development and investigation of the ALIGN idea is found in McCarthy and Prince 1993, which posits a general format for alignment constraints:
ALIGN(GCat-edge(L|R), PCat-edge(L|R) )
where GCat denotes a morphological or syntactic category; PCat denotes a prosodic category; L,R denote 'left' and 'right'.
A consonant-final MWord satisfies ALIGN only if its final C is a Coda. A vowel-final MWord satisfies ALIGN only if its final V is parsed as the Nucleus of an open syllable. MWords in which the final segment is not parsed at all will violate ALIGN because the morphological-category edge does not fall at a syllable edge. | Alan Prince and Paul Smolensky, 1993
ALLATIVE CASE
- (Grammar) Abbreviated ALL. A case that expresses motion to or toward the referent of the noun it marks.
The term allative case has been used in studies of Finnish and Eskimo. Its synonym additive case has been used especially in studies of Basque. (Pei and Gaynor 1954, Lyons 1968, Crystal 1985) | SIL Glossary of Linguistic Terms, 2003
- (Grammar) In a language like Finnish, the recipient role is expressed by the allative case, 'to something', 'onto something', which is opposed to the illative case, 'movement into' (see Newman 1998). Similarly, the English preposition to has a combined allative (path leading to a goal as the landmark) and recipient function. | Folke Josephson, 2007
ALLOCUTIVE
(Morphology) In the linguistics of Basque, allocutive verb forms are forms that vary depending on the social status of the addressee.
"Allocutivity refers to the encoding in the conjugated verb form of an addressee that is not an argument of the verb. Allocutivity is obligatory in Basque main clauses when the addressee is given familiar treatment." (Hualde and Ortiz de Urbina 2003) (Haase 1994) | Glottopedia, 2007
ALLOCUTIVE AGREEMENT
- (Syntax) Where a verb or functional element in the clause agrees not with the subject or some other argument, but with the addressee. For example, in certain dialects of Tamil, if you want to say I'm leaving to a single person who you use informal pronouns with, it would be Naan varreen. But if you say it to a group of people or an individual who you would use formal pronouns with, it's Naan varreen-nga.
Patterns like this are found in a number of languages. | Thomas McFadden, 2019
- (Morphology) A morphological feature in which the gender of an addressee is marked overtly in an utterance using fully grammaticalized markers (Trask 1997). The term was first used by Louis Lucien Bonaparte in 1862. | Wikipedia, 2016
ALLOCUTIVITY
(Grammar) The phenomenon I am referring to has been called allocutive "treatment" in Basque linguistics. I will name it allocutivity. It has not been an object of study in the generative framework, but has been carefully examined by several
authors (Lafon 1957, 1959, Rebuschi 1982, Alberdi Larizgoitia 1986). In allocutive forms, the inflected verb agrees with the addressee (person and gender agreement) when the latter is neither an argument selected by the verb. This is why in some traditional grammars allocutivity has been considered a voice (the so-called voix familière in Lafitte 1944). The following example illustrates allocutivity:
Lagunak
friend.ERG
ni
me.ACC
ikusi
seen
n-ai-k-Ø
1SG.ABS-+PR.AUX-2SG.MASC-3SG.ERG
'The friend saw me'
In (1) the auxiliary is inflected. It agrees with the subject (-Ø, 3d sg. ergative) and the object (prefix n-, 1st sg. absolutive). It also agrees with the addressee (-k, 2d sg. fam. masculine). In (1) the 2d person is not an argument, i.e. it is not selected by V. Furthermore, in the familiar register, this agreement is obligatory.
The phenomenon is reminiscent of the so-called Japanese performative honorific teinei-go, because it expresses the relationship between the speaker and the addressee (Harada 1976), but it is realized in a different way (Miyagawa 1987) and has a different syntactic distribution. | Bernard Beñat and B. Oyharçabal, 1993
ALLOMORPH
(Morphology) One of two or more complementary morphs which manifest a morpheme in its different phonological or morphological environments.
The allomorphs of a morpheme are derived from phonological rules and any morphophonemic rules that may apply to that morpheme.
Example: The plural morpheme in English has allomorphs [-s] as in hats, [-z] as in dogs, [-əz] as in boxes. (Hartmann and Stork 1972, Crystal 1985, Payne 1997) | SIL Glossary of Linguistic Terms, 2003
ALLOMORPHY
(Morphology) One morpheme surfaces with different phonological content (morph) in different contexts; i.e. one morpheme has multiple allomorphs.
Many different phenomena fall under the broad umbrella of allomorphy, running the gamut from purely phonological to purely morphological / lexical.
Carstairs-McCarthy (2001) lays out four main logically possible types. All types exist.
- a. Morphs phonetically similar, distribution describable in purely phonological terms.
b. Morphs phonetically dissimilar, distribution describable in purely phonological terms.
c. Morphs phonetically similar, distribution not describable in purely phonological terms.
d. Morphs phonetically dissimilar, distribution not describable in purely phonological terms.
| Sam Zukoff, 2018
ALTERNATIVE SEMANTICS
- (Semantics) Alternative semantics (Hamblin 1973) diverges from the standard type-theoretic framework for natural language semantics, rooted in Montague (1970, 1973), in that the semantic value of an expression is taken to be a set of objects in the expression's usual domain of interpretation, rather than a single object. For instance, the semantic value of a complete sentence is not a proposition but a set of propositions; the semantic value of an individual-denoting expression is not an individual but a set of individuals; and so on. Alternative semantics has been fruitfully applied to a range of linguistic phenomena, including questions (Hamblin 1973), focus (Rooth 1985), indeterminate pronouns (Shimoyama 2001, Kratzer and Shimoyama 2002), indefinites (Kratzer and Shimoyama 2002, Menéndez-Benito 2005, Aloni 2007), and disjunction (Simons 2005, Alonso-Ovalle 2006, Aloni 2007). | Ivano Ciardelli, Floris Roelofsen, and Nadine Theiler, 2017
- (Semantics) Or, Hamblin semantics. A framework in formal semantics and logic. In alternative semantics, expressions denote alternative sets, understood as sets of objects of the same semantic type. For instance, while the word Lena might denote Lena herself in a classical semantics, it would denote the singleton set containing Lena in alternative semantics. The framework was introduced by Charles Leonard Hamblin in 1973 as a way of extending Montague grammar to provide an analysis for questions. In this framework, a question denotes the set of its possible answers. Thus, if P and Q are propositions, then {P,Q} is the denotation of the question whether P or Q is true. Since the 1970s, it has been extended and adapted to analyze phenomena including focus (Krifka 1993), scope, disjunction (Fox 2007), NPIs (Chiercha 2001, 2013), presupposition, and implicature (Cross and Roelofsen 2014, Rooth 2016). | Wikipedia, 2022
ALTERNATIVE SET
(Semantics) A term used in relation to the semantics of focus for the set of items with which the denotation of a focused constituent contrasts. For example, in the sentence It was Mary who arrived late, the alternative set for Mary would include individuals other than Mary whom one might have expected would arrive late, but did not. | David Crystal, 2008
ALTERNATIVITY
- (Semantics) We here argue for an alternativity semantics for or, which treats or as a procedural, rather than truth-conditional expression at the core. On our analysis, or is silent about the truth of its disjuncts (that is, on how many of its disjuncts may or must be true). It only specifies that the explicitly mentioned disjuncts are associated with alternatives construed as mutually exclusive on some level.
Alternativity, we would like to emphasize, lies at the subjective, rather than the objective level (just like "contrast" and
"causality"). States of affairs by themselves may be either true or not, but they are not inherently "alternatives" to each other. It takes a subjective human eye to relate them, and to further impose "alternativity" on them. Consider in this connection the
following:
- Many treatments, including steroids, gabapentin, acupuncture, heat or ice, and spinal manipulation, have poor evidence for their use. (Wikipedia, Jan 29, 2017).
(1) lists a number of treatments for Sciatica, all claimed to be ineffective. Objectively, acupuncture, steroids etc. are on a par with heat and with ice. Indeed, the speaker could have used an and (or an or) throughout (e.g., [...] acupuncture, heat, ice and spinal manipulation), but that was not her choice. The relation between steroids and gabapentin etc. is subjectively construed differently from that between heat and ice. Only the latter two are explicitly profiled as alternatives to each other. They therefore constitute a single choice here. We will say that the writer allots only one slot to heat and to ice, despite the
fact that the two cannot simultaneously occupy that single slot. It is this restriction that construes the two as mutually
exclusive alternatives to each other. The other treatments are not so explicitly construed by the speaker, although, of course, in reality, they too are alternatives to each other. | Mira Ariel and Caterina Mauri, 2019
- (Semantics) The meaning of or has been considered the same as the logical connective ∨ (inclusive disjunction), which means that at least one disjunct is true. Ariel and Mauri (2018, 2019), examining the Santa Barbara Corpus, argue that inclusivity is too strong because the speaker may commit to none of the alternatives and too weak because she can commit to all alternatives. Instead, they suggest that the core meaning of or is alternativity on some level (the propositional level or a non-propositional level), which is procedural, non-truth-conditional and conventionally implicated. They classify or constructions according to the types of their "explicatures": Raised options, Higher-Level Category, Conjunctive, Narrowed, Choice, and Exhaustive readings. | E.J. Noh, 2020
- (Semantics) The essence of or constructions is alternativity (Ariel and Mauri 2019). An X or Y construction is simultaneously associated with (i) a set of distinct alternatives (X, Y) and (ii) a higher-level category which has (at least) X and Y as members. Consider (1):
- a. Diane: Who was the king or queen? (SBC: 023)
b. Patty: Was that World War Two, or World War One. (SBC: 023)
'King' and 'queen' are members of the higher-level category 'monarch', and 'World War Two' and 'World War One' are
members of the category of 'World War'. Not all higher-level categories are pre-established, however, and they may require ad
hoc constructing (Barsalou 1983). | Mira Ariel, 2018
Page Last Modified September 8, 2024